Post 2
Garfinkel’s linguistic vision
Garfinkel’s linguistic vision
A time for some rumination and
regurgitation.
The reading of Chapter 1 in Sidnell (2010)
helps shed some great light on the previous dense reading of Heritage,
interpreting Garfinkel’s view of language. For sociologists, the focus on language
use in a society, the talk or conversation, does not stem from an interest in
the nature of language itself, but from an interest in how language constitutes
actions. As Sidnell argues: “For a given occasion, there are specific places
within it at which point particular actions are relevantly done (can’t tell the
page number from my Kindle version).” And this corresponds with what I had
previous read from Bourdieu who also asserts that the meanings of social
actions are embedded in what is an unbroken chain of contingent inferences. The
ability to make these numerous inferences through contextualization is
illustrated by the anatomy of a simple 3-line conversation between a couple. What
is marvelous about this analysis of the structure or the “machinery”
(organization) of this seemingly explicit conversation is that it brings to
light our “seen but not noticed” subconscious norms that facilitate
communications, or in sociologist’s terms, that structure actions. During a
conversation, we usually depend on the other party’s understanding to design
and initiate a turn, to predict and monitor a response, and to probably adjust
our own talk by making sense of the other one’s explicit or more often than
not, implicit response and so on. These great abilities have so long been
internalized within us that they could have been reduced to oblivion if it were
not for the efforts of the linguists and the sociologists who examine the
relations between language and society.
Since these generally overlooked abilities are
nevertheless so intriguing if closely examined, they have attracted both
linguists and sociologists (and philosophers) alike, who have unequivocally
been seeking the answers for what they are. The search for linguistic
competency was first launched by Saussure who made a distinction between
“langue” (the inner language that stands for our universal language ability)
and “parole” (individual speech acts). For Saussure, it was “langue” that
should be the linguistic proper worth studying by linguists. Chomsky followed
the lead and created the phrase of “language competence”, which equals to human
being’s natural ability to formulate grammatical structures accepted by a
speech community even with very few exposure to the language when they are
young. This narrow definition of competency was later challenged and expanded
into larger realms by linguists from other schools of the discipline.
Incidentally, the later expansions can be paralleled with what Garfinkel has
envisioned:
“It is these capacities—the capacity to ‘understand’ a description,
to ‘make out’ from the description-in-its-context what the speaker is
understanding with the description and, with these resources, to determine what
the description presently ‘amounts to’—which constitute the defining characteristics
of “mastery of natural language’ or ‘membership’ (Heritage, p.155).”
As a former linguist myself, one of the
takeaways from Garfinkel is a better understanding of language itself. In the
midst of voices that lamented the paucity of our descriptive sources and
claimed the indexical character of natural language use as a defect, Garfinkel
proposed that it was our contextualization ability that permits “the
clarification and refinement of descriptors to the point that they can be
supplied with a sense that is adequate to their inferred task.” Simply put, it
is our ability to make inferences that enables the economy of our words or
language at large so that speakers can make sense with reasonably small
vocabulary. Given the fact that Garfinkel wrote before Chomsky, not to mention
before all those following linguists, his is indeed a visionary of great
insights.
With the circle of what comprises language
competency ever expanding, it is more and more realized that we rely on
structural, physical as well as logical, sociocultural knowledge about the
language action established through a process of socialization to function in a
society. It is also upon these common denominators (or the shared mundane knowledge)
within a speech community that a CA analyst is able to do the analyses because
he and his subjects see the world through the same lens of a language. Here
comes my doubt: am I qualified to analyze a language of which I am not a native
speaker?
a test of the comment function
ReplyDelete